Handouts
SkepticismDescartes is not a skeptic, though in the Meditations he gives a very vivid presentation of the skeptical argument. Descartes thinks he can defeat the skeptical argument, but many have found his reply to skepticism less than convincing. What the skeptic attempts to do is show that we do not know many things we might think we know; in particular, we know almost nothing about the external world. The skeptic does this by pointing to the possibility of a scenario in which everything seems just the same as it does to me now, but which is incompatible with knowledge. We considered a few such scenarios: that I am dreaming, that I am deceived by an evil demon, that I am a bodiless brain-in-a-vat being subject to experiments. So, the skeptic points out that:
This is logically equivalent to what Descartes suggests:
The scenario is supposed to be such that, if it did obtain, my experiences would be completely indistinguishable from what they are now. I cannot tell “from the inside” whether or not the scenario obtains.
Hence
If you think there are ways to tell dreaming from waking, what about the evil demon scenario, or the brain-in-a-vat Matrix scenario? The Dreaming ArgumentFrom David and Jean Blumenfeld, "Can I Know That I Am Not Dreaming?”
QuestionsIs the argument is valid—does the conclusion follows from the premises? Is it sound—are the premises true as well? (4) is just (C) from above. Let us for the moment grant that (4) is plausible. Does (6) follow from (4)? What about premise (7)? Notice that (7) is stronger that (A). (1) says that if know I have hands, not only must it be true that I am not merely dreaming it, I must also know that I am not merely dreaming it. Why should we accept this? Suppose one holds, as Descartes at times seems to, that knowledge requires absolute certainty. One thing this could mean is that knowledge requires evidence sufficient to rule out all alternatives. The possibility of dreaming (or an evil demon, or of being a brain-in-a-vat) is supposed to inject doubt into any belief we have about the external world because it is a possibility we cannot rule out. So: if knowing that I have hands requires being absolutely certain I have hands, then to know I would have to eliminate all doubts. To do that, I would have rule out the possibility that I am merely dreaming. This is very close to what (7) requires. |
Anselm’s Ontological Argument
|
Free Will and CompatibilismA paradox is a set of statements each of which enjoys some plausibility yet which cannot all be true.
(D), (F), and (I) each enjoy some plausibility, yet they cannot all be true. We have a paradox. The Compatibilist ResolutionFreedom is opposed to constraint or coercion, not to necessity. We are free insofar as we are not prevented by constraint or coercion from doing what we want.
The Humean compatibilist rejects the principle of alternative possibilities, substituting (c), and (c) is compatible with determinism. It may be determined that Tana will want to A and that she will A; all that matters for her freedom is that had she (been determined to) wanted to B, she would have been able to.
There are counterexamples to this analysis that were mentioned in class (the unwilling addict, the mad scientist who controls your desires). But even setting these aside, many people initially find the compatibilist analysis unsatisfying. Surely, you say, there has to be more to freedom that this. It’s the compatibilist job to deflate such opposition to his analysis. Deflating ObjectionsMorally appraisable action requires causation You might be unsatisfied because you feel that even with compatibilist freedom, your body is still just a puppet at the end of a long causal chain. Hume notes that for a bit of behavior to count as Tana’s action, it must be caused by her beliefs and desires. We depend on the fact that desires and beliefs lead to behavior.
Thus the compatibilist claims the problem cannot be with the fact that our actions have causes. Choosing our desires You might still feel unsatisfied because it seems like on the compatibilist picture we are stuck with the beliefs and desires we have. Is this really a problem? We make our choices in part by considering what we want. We do not think it an impingement on our freedom that we don’t also get to choose our desires. Does it even make sense for us to choose all of our desires? Tana freely chooses her dessert. She opts for pecan pie over chocolate soufflé because she wants the pie more than the soufflé.
I hope it’s clear that we are either off on an unsatisfiable regress, or that Tana picks her desires at random. Is this really what we think freedom requires? Does it require having wants about wants about wants…(ad infinitum)? Does it require Tana pick all of her desires at random? The compatibilist says no — any feeling of dissatisfaction with compatibilism on these grounds is unjustified. |
Thomson’s Defense of AbortionTraditionally the focus in the abortion debate is on whether the unborn fetus is a person. This focus is misguided, Thomson argues, because even if we grant that the fetus is a person, there are still cases where abortion is morally permissible. Thomson grants, then, that the fetus has the right to life. She questions whether it follows that the fetus has the right to the mother’s body.
The reasoning in the first two cases Thomson considers is straightforward.
Consensual SexThis secures the permissibility of abortion in only a narrow range of circumstances. What about pregnancy that results from consensual sex? It appears that Thomson believes the famous violinist analogy extends even to cases of pregnancy from consensual sex. Perhaps the easiest way to examine this issue is by considering reasons to think that a mother has special responsibility to a fetus if conceived by consensual sex (i.e. that the famous violinist case is not analogous to pregnancy due to consensual sex), and to see what Thomson’s replies might be. Consent Objection If a woman consents to becoming pregnant, she has special responsibility to the fetus. Thus a mother who became pregnant intentionally certainly may not abort it. A woman who engages in sex (protected or unprotected) may not desire a pregnancy, but she nonetheless tacitly consents to it if it occurs. We can see this by appealing to the following principle:
In our case, when a woman engages in consensual sex knowing that it might lead to pregnancy, if it does lead to pregnancy, she has consented to the pregnancy.
Responsibility to the innocent Maybe what the replies bring out is that consent is really not what’s at issue. We can incur responsibilities without consent.
Most women realize that consensual sex may lead to the creation of a helpless innocent person, and they are thus responsible for the well-being of that person (at least while its helpless, but possibly longer).
|